Contents Previous Chapter
Next Chapter
Chapter II
Main Ideological Currents Leading up to Marxism
The Enlightment
Bourgeois Liberalism
Classical Political Economy
Socialist Theories
German Classical Philosophy
An analysis
of the socio-economic and political conditions of the late eighteenth
and early nineteenth century thus points to the inevitable birth then of
proletarian ideology. However, in order to understand the specific
content and form of Marxism it is necessary to understand the process of
development of human ideas and thought in the most advanced countries at
that time. Since it was capitalism that was the leading force in the
development of human societies and since Western Europe was the seat of
most of capitalist development it was but natural that Marxism based
itself and drew upon all that was best in European thought. Let us
therefore examine the state and progress of the principal streams of
advanced European thought at that time.
The Enlightenment
The
intellectual and ideological background to the birth of Marxism was the
progressive and often revolutionary movement which dominated the world
of ideas during the eighteenth century at the time of the emergence of
capitalism. It was linked to the struggle of the nascent bourgeoisie and
the popular masses against feudal practices and institutions. This
movement was called the Enlightenment.
The basic
content of the Enlightenment ideology was rationalist and humanist, with
a firm belief in the progress of man. It believed that human history was
an ascent, rather than a decline or an up-down movement about a level
trend. The Enlightenment drew its strength mainly from the growth of
production and trade and the economic and scientific rationality
believed to be associated with both. Its main ideologues saw that man’s
scientific knowledge and technical control over nature increased daily.
They thus believed that human society and individual man could be
perfected by the same application of reason, and were destined to be so
perfected by history. This core Enlightenment belief in the united
progress of reason and freedom provided the basis for revolutionary
bourgeois ideology, i.e., classical bourgeois liberalism. This core
belief also continued into the first socialist thinkers in the
nineteenth century.
The
distinctive feature of the Enlightenment was the urge of the thinkers
concerned to restructure all social relations on a basis of Reason,
Eternal Justice, Equality and other principles, stemming, in their
opinion, from Nature itself, from the inalienable "natural rights" of
Man. The leading figures of the Enlightenment saw the dissemination of
progressive ideas and knowledge and the enhancement of moral standards
to be the basic means of transforming the life of society. As Engels put
it, the ideals of the Enlightenment were in practice none other than the
"idealised kingdom of the bourgeoisie". Its greatest supporters and
champions were the economically most progressive classes, those most
directly involved in the advances of the time : the mercantile circles
and economically enlightened landlords, financiers,
scientifically-minded economic and social administrators, the educated
middle class, manufacturers and entrepreneurs. Naturally the two chief
centres of the Enlightenment were also those of the dual revolution -
France and England.
A secular,
rationalist and progressive individualism dominated ‘enlightened’
thought. To set the individual free from the shackles which fettered him
was its chief object: from the ignorant traditionalism of the Middle
Ages, which still threw their shadow across the world, from the
superstition of the churches, from the irrationality which divide men
into a hierarchy of higher and lower ranks according to birth. Liberty,
equality and fraternity of all men were its slogans. In due course they
became those of the French Revolution.
The
Enlightenment in England, which followed its bourgeois revolution, was
relatively moderate in its ideas and goals. Its leading figure, John
Locke, as well as other representatives, propagated in both religion and
politics a spirit of class compromise. In France however the
Enlightenment preceded the Revolution and played a decisive part in the
ideological preparation for it. The fathers of the French Enlightenment
were Voltaire and Montesquieu and it was known for its militant
anticlericalism and its unswerving opposition to the Roman Catholic
religion and Church, which constituted the spiritual bastion of the
feudal, absolutist order. The Enlightenment in America was led by the
radical democratic wing who took part in the War of Independence
(1775-1783)- Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Paine, Thomas Jefferson and
others. In Russia one of the trends of the Enlightenment included
figures who were members of the first modern Russian revolutionary
insurrectionary movement, that of the Decembrists (1825). Thus
Enlightenment thought often played the revolutionary role of providing
the philosophical and ideological basis for the bourgeois revolutions.
Bourgeois Liberalism
Up to the
French Revolution the most powerful and advanced formulation of the
Enlightenment ideology of progress had been classical bourgeois
liberalism. It was rigorously rationalist and secular; that is to say
convinced on the one hand of the ability of men in principle to
understand all and to solve all questions by the use of reason, and on
the other hand of the tendency of irrational behaviour and institutions
like organised non-rational religion to obscure rather than enlighten.
Philosophically it tended towards materialism or empiricism. Its general
assumptions regarding the world and man were marked by an intense
individualism.
In brief, for
classical liberalism the human world consisted of self contained
individual atoms with certain built-in passions and drives, each seeking
above all to maximise his satisfactions and minimise his
dissatisfactions, equal in this to all others, and ‘naturally’
recognising no limits or rights of interference with his urges. In other
words, each man was ‘naturally’ possessed of life, liberty and the
pursuit of happiness, as the American Declaration of Independence put
it. In the course of pursuing this self-interest, each individual in
this anarchy of equal competitors, found it advantageous or unavoidable
to enter into certain relations with other individuals, and this complex
of useful arrangements - which was often referred to as a social
‘contract’ - constituted society and social or political groups. Of
course, social arrangements or associations meant some reduction of
man’s ‘naturally’ unlimited liberty to do what he liked, one of the
tasks of politics being to reduce such interference to the practicable
minimum. Social aims were therefore the arithmetical sum of individual
aims. Happiness was each individual’s supreme object; the greatest
happiness of the greatest number, was the aim of society.
Though this
in theory was the political outlook of liberalism, in actual practice
the bourgeoisie did not go according to this pattern. This was because
the greatest happiness of the greatest numbers and the pursuit of
rational self-interest could also be interpreted to include rational
interference by the state in the bourgeois rights of private property,
enterprise and individual freedom. Thus in practice it was ensured that
these rights of the bourgeoisie were safeguarded from any state
interference or submission to the requirements of rationality. Thus
England’s John Locke put private property as the most basic of ‘natural
rights’; and the French Revolution’s Declaration of the Rights of Man
and Citizen was modified to bring the demand for free enterprise under
the form of a general natural right to liberty.
Classical Political Economy
The essence
of the bourgeois liberal ideology was carried forward in the most
thorough fashion in the works of the classical political economists.
This new field of study naturally reached its heights in the mother
country of the Industrial Revolution — Britain. Its period started with
the publication of Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations in 1776, it
reached its peak with David Ricardo’s Principles of Political Economy
in 1817, and from 1830 onwards started the period of its decline or
transformation. Adam Smith (1723-90) argued that the self-interested
competitive activities of independent individuals, when left to operate
as far as possible unchecked, produced not only a ‘natural’ social
order, but also the most rapid possible increase in the ‘wealth of
nations’, i.e. the comfort and well-being, and therefore the happiness,
of all men. The basis of this natural order was the social division of
labour. He therefore logically proved that the existence of a class of
capitalists owning the means of production benefited all, including the
class of labourers hiring themselves out to the capitalists. He thus
also similarly proved that both Britain and Jamaica were best served by
the one producing manufactured goods and the other raw sugar. Moreover,
according to him, the economically very unequal society which resulted
inevitably from the operations of human nature was not incompatible with
the natural equality of all men or with justice. This was supposedly
because even the poorest was ensured a better life than he would
otherwise have had. Further, it was based on the most equal of all
relationships, the exchange of equivalents in the market. Thus, in Adam
Smith’s view, progress was as natural as capitalism. Remove the
artificial obstacles to it which the past had erected, and it must
inevitably take place. And the progress of production went hand in hand
with that of the arts, the sciences and civilisation in general.
This
comforting view of the all-conquering nature of capitalism gained
acceptance not merely because of what was then believed to be the
unanswerable nature of its deductive reasoning. More than that its basis
lay in the very visible progress of eighteenth century capitalism and
European civilisation. However when there were marked difficulties in
capitalist expansion from around 1810 to the 1840s the mood changed.
Optimism changed to criticism and there started a period of critical
enquiry, particularly into distribution as against production, which had
been the main concentration of economists during Adam Smith’s time.
The work of
David Ricardo (1792-1823) belongs to this period. He was an economist
who participated wholeheartedly in the practical issues affecting the
capitalist class of the day. He thus was a champion of the cause of free
trade and opposition to landlords, issues which he also supported by
economic theory. However he also pointed out contradictions in the
capitalist system which Smith had overlooked. One important such point
was the tendency of the rate of profit to decline. More significant
however was his basic general labour theory of value. It pointed out,
for the first time, that labour was the source of all value and that the
capitalists and landlords appropriated in the form of profit and rent
respectively the surplus which the worker produced over and above what
he received back as wages. Ricardo however did not lead his labour
theory of value to its logical social conclusions. He did not clearly
point out that the capitalist in fact exploited the worker and it was
necessary to do away with capitalists to do away with exploitation. A
group of Ricardian ‘labour economists’ however soon arose in Britain who
made this analysis.
Such analysis
and critique of capitalism would however not have gained much weight if
the earlier period of continuous rapid capitalist expansion had
continued. However the capitalist system had started facing crises,
first the localised crises in particular manufacturing and financial
sectors of the economy from 1793, and then the all encompassing periodic
general crises of 1825-26, 1836-37, 1839-42, 1846-48, etc. Economists
like Sismondi, Wade and others too had started locating the cause of the
crises in the nature of the capitalist system itself. In such a
situation it was therefore but natural that as contradictions sharpened,
particularly after 1830, even Ricardian theories started being looked
upon with suspicion by the bourgeoisie. In fact some bourgeois writers
saw Ricardo as the source of inspiration for agitators and disrupters in
society. While such direct and immediate inspiration from Ricardo’s
works may have not been that significant, he definitely provided the
groundwork for a much more serious and enduring offensive on the basis
of capitalism. It was his labour theory of value and other contributions
of the classical economists that Marx developed upon while making his
critique of capital.
Socialist Theories
Meanwhile as
classical bourgeois liberalism started losing much of its Enlightenment
confidence in the inevitability and desirability of progress, a new
ideology, socialism, started reformulating the truths of the eighteenth
century. Reason, science and progress were its firm foundation. The
socialists of this period were thus no mere repetition of dreamers in a
perfect society of common ownership that periodically appear throughout
history. They did not long for the return of some idyllic pre-industrial
society. Rather their distinguishing feature was that they all accepted
the Industrial Revolution which created the very possibility of modern
socialism. They attempted to take the industrial society forward to a
more rational, more scientific stage.
The first
active manifestation of socialism after the French Revolution was the
conspiracy of Gracchus Babeuf. Babeuf and the Babouvists took their
philosophy in the main from Rousseau and the utopianists of the
Enlightenment. Their basic premise was the idea of equality. They thus
aimed at the abolition of private property, equal distribution of wealth
irrespective of the work done, no right to inheritance, no large cities,
and that all would be compelled to do physical work and live in the same
manner. The Babouvists planned to seize power through a conspiracy, and
then the conspirators were supposed to rule on behalf of the masses,
until the people were educated and able to rule through elected bodies.
Babeuf’s conspiracy was detected in 1796 and he was executed. His ideas
were to some extent carried on by Louis Blanqui. The Babouvist programme
was not expressed in specific class categories but merely talked in
terms of rich and poor or people and tyrants. It however was one of the
first attempts at an economic criticism of private property as the
foundation of society.
Henri
Saint-Simon (1760-1825) is however normally recognised as the real
founder of modern theoretical socialism, conceived not merely as an
ideal but as the outcome of a historical process. He formulated the
principle of a future ‘organic’ social community to which industrial
concentration was leading. This future society would be one where
production would be planned and measured by social needs, where private
property would be subordinated to the general good and where inheritance
would be abolished. The social hierarchy would no longer be hereditary;
the highest positions would be held by wise men supervising the general
development of society. The new industrial order would put an end to the
misery of the proletariat, but the oppressed workers would not be the
class to implement Saint-Simon’s plans. According to him, the
transformation would be carried out by manufacturers, bankers, scholars,
and artists, once they had been convinced by the new doctrine. To bring
about this change nothing more was needed than peaceful reforms such as
the acquisition of parliamentary power by industrialists; Saint-Simon
also appealed to the governing class to support his plan. The most
important features of his doctrine may be listed as follows : the firm
belief in the regularity of history and its inexorable march towards
socialism; the ruinous consequences of anarchic competition and the
necessity of state economic planning; the replacement of political
government by economic administration; science as the instrument of
social progress; and the internationalist approach to politico-economic
problems. Some negative features were Saint-Simon’s idea that the state
as it now exists can be used to bring about a socialist transformation;
his appeal for co-operation between classes, and the religious character
he gave to his industrial order. In later years after his death Saint-Simonism
became somewhat of a sect with his followers often stressing the
religious aspects of his teachings. Its influence however continued
through various prominent individuals. The socialist Louis Blanc was a
disciple of Saint-Simon and through him was Lassalle, the pioneer
political organiser of the German working class. In the field of
industry one of Saint-Simon’s disciples built the Suez Canal whereas
another became the manager of a railway line. In fact of all the
pre-Marxist socialist doctrines Saint-Simonism had the strongest effect
in spreading socialist ideas among the educated classes in various parts
of Europe.
Robert Owen
(1771-1858) was the other influential socialist thinker of this period.
His main theoretical work was A New View of Society (1813-14),
through which he tried to convince manufacturers and the aristocracy of
the need for a reform of the industrial and monetary system, wages and
education, in the interest not only of the workers but of capitalists
and the whole of society. In numerous subsequent pamphlets, periodicals,
articles, memorandums and appeals to Parliament he continued to
advocated his reformist ideas, exposing the horrors of industrialisation
and urging the adoption of social and educational measures which would
remedy abuses without hindering technical progress. He was one of the
main forces behind legislation restricting the working hours for
children. Due to his intense propaganda against religion and private
property he came under severe attack in Britain. He therefore left for
America where he unsuccessfully attempted to set up communist
settlements. However when he returned to Britain he became the first
outstanding organiser of the trade union and workers co-operative
movement. In his later years Owen put his trust in communist settlements
engaged in agriculture and industry, the nuclei of the future harmonious
society. Here, he believed that thanks to good organisation and loyal
co-operation, people would produce more willingly, in greater quantity,
and at a cheaper rate than elsewhere. Although it originated in
practical experience, Owen’s doctrine, like that of the French
socialists, centred round the conviction that socialism was a unique
discovery, so manifestly right that it was bound to be accepted by all
classes as soon as proclaimed. Owen thought that a radical economic
reform in a socialist spirit could be effected by appealing to universal
human interests and with the aid of the existing state power. Owen’s
doctrine initiated a new phase of the British workers’ movement, in
which it ceased to be merely an outburst of despair and became a
systematic force. However, the British trade union movement is still
marked by his outlook, which directly subordinates the political
struggle to economic interests. The social democratic theories which
treated workers’ political parties as organs of the trade unions are a
continuation of the same doctrine.
Charles
Fourier (1772-1837), was the one who described the future socialist
society in greater detail than any of the other socialists of his time.
Fourier’s doctrine was inspired by the phenomena of crisis, speculation,
exploitation, and the misery of the workers. All this, he thought was
due to a wrongful system of labour and exchange. Human needs and
passions were ineradicable, but they only led to unhappiness because
society was badly organised; the problem was to order matters in such a
way that they led to the general good instead of to antagonism. To
achieve this Fourier drew up an elaborate system of society composed of
basic units of 2000 persons each called phalanxes. Unlike Saint-Simon
and Owen, he did not see the remedy in the transformation of human
nature but in a new social order where conflict of interests would be so
organised as to lead to harmony. His disciples while giving up the more
fantastic portions of Fourier’s theory tried to modify his ideas in the
direction of realism. Workers’ consumer co-operatives were an outcome of
his system, as were attempts to establish producer co-operatives in
which the workers were shareholders.
Besides these
principal figures there were many other socialists contributing to the
immense outpouring of socialist literature of this period. Among them
was Wilhelm Weitling (1808-71) a German emigrant worker who presented
communism as a Christian ideal. He presented an intense critique of
capitalism from a class viewpoint and unlike many of the prominent
socialists, did not expect the government or the capitalists to
recognise his ideal and bring it about of their own accord ; he believed
that the workers can rely only on themselves and on their own strength.
Etienne Cabet (1788-1856) was another socialist who wrote extensively
advocating a non-revolutionary communism as the teaching of Christ. He
later emigrated to America to establish communist settlements there.
Pierre Joseph Proudhon (1809-65) was another prolific writer. Regarded
as the father of modern anarchism, he painted the picture of a future
society operated by ‘free mutualist associations’; a system which he
called anarchy. A figure who was not much of a theoretician but was of
immense practical significance in the principal revolutionary events of
the time - both the 1848 Revolution and the Paris Commune - was Louis-Auguste
Blanqui (1805-81). He continued the Babouvist tradition of revolutionary
conspiracy into the workers’ movement and was a strong proponent and
practitioner of armed insurrection. In a vague and broad sense he also
accepted communism and the conception of dictatorship of the
proletariat. Louis Blanc (1811-82) on the other hand was the successor
of the Saint-Simonist tradition and is considered one of the chief
precursors of the welfare state. He believed that it was possible,
without violence or mass expropriation, to carry out peaceful economic
reforms within a system of political and industrial democracy which
would eliminate poverty and harmful competition and would gradually lead
to social equality and to the socialisation of means of production.
This
substantial body of socialist thought as can be seen emanated mainly
from France, which was at that time the main centre for secret
revolutionary groups and communist organisations. While socialists
branched out in different directions, in essence this thought was a
continuation of the Enlightenment spirit and ideas of rationalism and
progress. However socialism was at the same time a break with the
individualism, self-interest and competition of bourgeois liberalism. It
was the ideology representing the initial hopes and aspirations of the
infant proletariat.
German Classical Philosophy
Whereas
British classical political economy representing the revolutionary
modern bourgeoisie and French socialist theory representing the infant
proletariat had a clear-cut progressive and also revolutionary content,
the position was quite ambiguous with regard to German classical
philosophy — the other great and influential body of European thought at
the turn of the nineteenth century. It occupied an ideological position
between the progressive and the anti-progressive, or in social terms,
between the industrial bourgeoisie and proletariat on one side, and the
aristocratic, mercantile and feudal classes on the other. It represented
the contradictions and complexities of the German middle classes, who
while in some ways believing in progress, were at the same time not
prepared to follow it to its logical liberal or socialist conclusions.
This because they were too weak and too frightened (after the experience
of the Jacobin radical phase of the French Revolution) to challenge the
power of the princes whose officials they often were. Thus the views of
this group combined the liberal with the anti-liberal, the progressive
with the anti-progressive. Further, this essential complexity and
contradictoriness allowed them to see more deeply into the nature of
society than either liberal progressives or anti-progressives. It in a
way forced them into dialectics.
The German
middle class contained a disproportionately large number of civil
servants and state-employed professors. This affected the views of this
class which had very few classical liberals. A belief in the
inevitability of progress and in the benefits of scientific and economic
advance, combined with a belief in the virtues of an enlightened
paternal or bureaucratic administration and a sense of responsibility
among the upper sections was the common opinion. German moderate
liberalism was best represented by middle class demands to be
implemented by an enlightened state.
The
fundamental atmosphere of German thought - whether in philosophy,
science or the arts - differed markedly from the main tradition of the
eighteenth century in Western Europe. Perhaps since its members had
neither the power to overthrow their societies nor the economic
resources to make an Industrial Revolution, they tended to concentrate
on the construction of elaborate general systems of thought. The
persistence of the intellectual atmosphere of the last age in which
Germany had been economically, intellectually, and to some extent
politically, predominant, largely accounts for it. Due to the decline in
the period between the Reformation and the later eighteenth century the
archaism of the German intellectual tradition had been largely
preserved. And at a time when the classical eighteenth century view was
approaching its limits, this gave German thought some advantage, and
helps to explain its increasing intellectual influence in the nineteenth
century. The most impressive and influential expression of German
thought was German classical philosophy created basically between 1760
and 1830. Its two great figures were Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) and
George Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831).
Kant first
expounded his ideas in his Critique of Pure Reason in 1781. Among
his significant positive ideas are his insistence that independently of
our consciousness and outside it there exists an objective world
(‘things in themselves’); the attempt to examine the Earth and the Solar
System in their emergence and development; his investigation of the
sources and forms of knowledge; his identification of a number of
contradictions intrinsic to knowledge and reality. Some potentially
reactionary aspects of Kant’s thinking are: his teaching regarding the
fundamental impossibility of cognizing (‘things in themselves’); the
impossibility of surmounting the barrier separating phenomena,
accessible to human knowledge, and their essence that is inaccessible to
it; Kant’s efforts to reconcile materialism and idealism, scientific
knowledge and religious faith.
Hegel
elaborated a philosophical system , in which "the whole world, natural,
historical, intellectual, is represented as a process, i.e., as in
constant motion, change, transformation, development; and the attempt is
make to trace out the internal connection that makes a continuous whole
of all the movement and development" (Engels, Anti-Duhring, p.
34). Hegel’s system consists of three parts: Logic, Philosophy of Nature
and Philosophy of the Spirit. In the first part he considers the
progress of thought in the divine mind up until the creation of Nature,
in the second he examines the development of that thought within created
Nature, and, thirdly, its return to itself in the human spirit. The
essential core of this system is provided by the ideas concerning the
historical advance of man’s knowledge and social consciousness,
presented in the context of dialectics.
German
classical philosophy was a thoroughly bourgeois phenomenon. All its
leading figures hailed the French Revolution and remained loyal to it
for a considerable time. The Enlightenment was the framework of Kant’s
thought and the starting point of Hegel’s. The philosophy of both was
deeply immersed in the idea of progress and Hegel’s entire philosophy is
one of evolution and necessary progress. Further, both studied the
British political economists and were probably influenced to some extent
by Adam Smith. Hegel even used in an abstract manner the tools of the
classical liberal economists in his formulation of labour as a
fundamental factor in humanity. All this firmly established German
classical philosophy’s bourgeois roots.
Nevertheless,
from the very beginning it differed from classic liberalism in important
respects. This was more apparent in the case of Hegel. In the first
place German philosophy was deliberately idealist, rejecting the
materialism or empiricism of the classical tradition. In the second
place, Hegel, unlike the classical liberals, makes his starting point
the collective and not the individual. Moreover, German thinkers not
being central participants in the bourgeois-liberal advance, were much
more aware of its limits and contradictions. While recognising the
inevitability of bourgeois society’s triumphant progress, they also
raised the question of whether it may not in turn be superseded. In
theory the transitoriness of the historically doomed society was built
into their philosophy itself.
However in
practice the philosophers tried to reconcile this revolutionary nature
of their philosophical conclusions with reality in a conservative
manner. This Hegel did through a process of idealisation of the Prussian
state and a refusal to accept its transitoriness, as also an attempt to
end history with the cognition of the Absolute Idea. However this lay in
direct contradiction to the core substance of a philosophy which saw the
historical process itself developing through the dialectic of
contradictions. This contradiction could not obviously stand up to the
years of ferment following 1830. Just as we saw a process of decline in
classical political economy in this period, we can also see a period of
disintegration in German classical philosophy. The ‘Young Hegelians’
refused to halt where their teacher did and insisted on following their
philosophy to its logical conclusions. They further showed their
readiness to take the road of revolution abandoned by their
predecessors. However the issues of revolution in the 1830-48 period
were no longer simply the question of the seizure of power by bourgeois
liberals. A new class — the proletariat — had emerged and started
rewriting the agenda of history. Therefore the intellectual
revolutionary to emerge from the disintegration of German philosophy was
not some bourgeois radical but Karl Marx.
In fact 1830
which marked the revival of the major west -European revolutionary
movement, also marked the beginning of the crisis of classical bourgeois
ideology. Its most advanced fields - political economy and philosophy -
were in a process of decline and disintegration. The changing material
conditions of the bourgeoisie and the apparent obstacles to its
triumphal advance prevented the contemporary bourgeois thinkers from
carrying forward uninterruptedly the classical tradition of Adam Smith
and Ricardo or of Kant and Hegel. The great tradition of the
intellectual development following from the Enlightenment however did
not die. It was transformed into its opposite in the form of Marxism. |